INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM ESSAY -- DRAFT 2

 

     Throughout the years that I have been teaching

librarianship, I have been responsible for explaining the concept

of intellectual freedom to students. A typical explanation

includes a statement of what the concept means and a brief

discussion of why the librarian has a professional obligation to

support it. During the discussion I have also emphasized that not

everyone in the society agrees with the primacy of intellectual

freedom. This means that the librarian must be prepared to defend

that principle against  censorship of all sorts.  The conflict is

set in the form of a morality tale. The librarian in shining

armor repels the forces of darkness that threaten our right to

read. The dark force is embodied in the scurrilous person of the

censor.

 

     As time has passed, I have witnessed numerous formal and

informal encounters between defenders of the librarians' faith

and those who argue for censorship. (include some examples) When

I have reflected on the nature of these encounters, two strong

impressions have gradually infiltrated my consciousness. The

first is that there is never any meeting of minds in these

encounters. There is no evidence that either party ever

understands the position of the other. They just talk at one

another.

 

     The other impression that has emerged is the observation that the

censor sees himself as a figure in shining armor who struggles to

repel the forces of darkness represented by the scurrilous figure of

the librarian. I have been surprised to find that the morality play is

as real for our adversaries as it is for us, but the masks are

reversed. Each of us, censor and librarian, is the hero in defense of

a pure idea. For each, the opponent is misguided at best, at worst a

villain.

 

     I have always been a relativist, uncomfortable with absolutes. It

has been a shock to recognize that the absolutism I have deplored in

the censor has its mirror image in the arguments I have provided in

defense of the librarian's commitment to intellectual freedom. This

insight has left me exceedingly uneasy. It has shattered the

persuasive power inherent in the imagery of the morality play. This

has led to the search for a new foundation for the defense of

intellectual freedom.

 

     I began to seek some more satisfactory explanation for the

dynamics of the  relationship between librarians and intellectual

freedom and eventually arrived at writings which treat the underlying

concept of freedom in general.

 

     Now "freedom", as you know, is not an idea that lends itself to

easy distillation. As a philosophical concept it is one of the

fundamental building blocks that contribute to the perennial

consideration of those characteristics that describe the human

condition. Other such philosophical imponderables include  "reality",

"truth", "goodness", "knowing", and "beauty". One of the features of

each of these concepts which renders it of continuing interest to the

speculative thinker is the range of possibilities which the idea

embraces. These are intellectual constructs whose meanings have eluded

a consensus of agreement despite millenia of intense debate.

 

     Another consideration which complicates the evaluation of

the idea of freedom is the fact that for most people, freedom is

a loaded word. Rare is the philosopher or polemicist who is

prepared to argue that "freedom", however defined, is an

undesirable characteristic, and the occasional exception is

inevitably considered to be satirical or perverse. This means

that whatever the commentator's attitude toward those elements of

political or social activity that are being considered, the term

"freedom" is likely to be used to describe some dimension of the

activity that is being advocated while it is denied by definition

to the other side, which is characterized as misusing the term.

(example here?)

 

     Anyone who seeks to study the nature of freedom as an abstract

idea is soon made aware that there are turbulent controversies that

surround its meaning. Philosophers disagree concerning the nature of

freedom, they disagree about how freedom relates to other social

values, and they disagree about the effects of various proposals for

achieving freedom. (fn 7 INTFREE) Any analysis of the meaning of

freedom as a concept requires some method for imposing order on the

vast body of conflicting opinion that has accumulated throughout the

more than two thousand years that span the history of recorded thought

on the subject. With a topic as rich and value-laden as the idea of

freedom, classification of the meanings attributed to the term has

been neither easy nor uncontroversial. (fn 8 INTFREE)

 

     Whatever the ultimate conclusion of the particular analysis, one

distinction emerges with some regularity. In its most simplified form,

this is a distinction between  (1) freedom as the absence of coercion

and (2) freedom as the capacity to act according to some ideal. The

differences between these two categories of freedom may not be

readily apparent, but in fact the distinction not only has

significance for advancing the abstract understanding of freedom

as a force in intellectual history. It suggests an explanation

that can be used to construct a more helpful new model for the

ongoing struggle between supporters of intellectual freedom and

would-be censors. Let me explain.

 

     Freedom as the absence of coercion has acquired such labels as

"negative freedom" and the "circumstantial freedom of self-

realization". Freedom as the capacity to act according to some ideal

has been called "positive freedom" and "the acquired freedom of self-

perfection".(fn 9 & 10 INTFREE) Since the labels have themselves

become grounds for controversy, (fn 11 INTFREE) the two categories

shall be referred to as F1 and F2 during this discussion.

 

     F1 is concerned with the capacity of the individual to act as an

independent agent. It provides that each person shall not be deprived

from pursuing his/her own interest, wherever such interest may lead.

It is the freedom to which philosophers like John Stuart Mill refer

when they speak optimistically of what they perceive as the necessary

connection between the opportunity to act independently and the

advancement of the society toward a more perfected condition. F1 is

the Jeffersonian ideal of freedom which is most prominently expressed

in the political documents of the American revolution. It is the

freedom whereof civil libertarians speak when they call for the right

to pursue any idea, and it conveys the librarian's sense of

intellectual freedom.         (examples?)

 

     F2 is concerned with the capacity to act according to an ideal.

This freedom consists of being one's own master, not in the sense of

being able to carry out any action that the individual desires, but

rather in the sense of learning to live in a way that conforms to a

defined pattern of right thinking. The person acquires dominance over

his passions and conquers the impulse toward self-destructive behavior

in order to achieve some set of goals. These goals are often defined

by an external standard rather than being conceived  in the mind of

the individual with whose freedom we are concerned. Kant seems to be

referring to F2 when he says that "Virtue, therefore, in so far as it

is based on internal freedom, contains a positive command for man,

namely, that he should bring all his powers and inclinations  under

his rule (that of reason) . . . since, unless reason takes the reins

of government in its own hands, the feelings and inclinations play the

master over the man." (fn 12 INTFREE) Any person who feels that true

freedom derives from living successfully according to the golden rule

embraces F2. So does the individual who believe that spiritual freedom

is achieved through the practice of some defined discipline of

meditation, exercise and renunciation of material values. Every

philosophy that has some prescription for living at its core advocates

a kind of F2.

 

     It should be quite clear by now that F1 and F2 involve distinctly

different conceptions of freedom. How would someone who espouses F2 be

likely to react to a description of F1? Individual responses would

surely differ, but many persons who feel that true freedom consists of

the capacity to act according to a specialized ideal would not find

the F1 ability to take action without constraint to be worth much. In

fact, the person who is working toward the realization of an F2 ideal

through a program of disciplined self-control is quite likely to

perceive the blandishments of values associated with F1 as a threat, a

siren song of anarchy. And what of the F1 believer? To this person,

the argument that freedom is a direct consequence of the surrender of

will to some externally derived program of action would seem to be an

invitation to subjugation. In each case, freedom for one is apt to

seem like unfreedom to the other.

 

     The careful reader has noted by now that the positions

associated with these two definitions of freedom reflect the

morality play of intellectual freedom versus censorship. The F1

freedom to pursue one's own interest wherever it leads provides a

script where the librarian is center stage and the hero of the

piece. Her duty is to provide all the information that is

relevant to a customer's need without questioning the use to

which the information will be put or the moral correctness of the

information sources. The villain is the would-be censor who lurks

around the fringes of the set, seeking an opportunity to

interdict the flow of information to persons of whom he does not

approve or to filter the information to remove impurities that

may endanger the customer's moral good health. He is the 

coercer, who would limit the freedom of the librarian and the

customer to pursue their own information related interests. It is

F1 freedom that is celebrated here.

 

     In the alternative scenario, the star of the show is the

kindly, wise and concerned censor. Through some combination of

grace, good works and self-discipline he knows the truth about

life. His freedom is defined by the degree to which he can

successfully conform to the goals that are defined by his

discovered ideals of right living. The star of this play does not

necessarily follow ideals which include the need to act as a

censor. In theory, the ideals that determine his behavior could

demand impeccable respect for everyone else's right to destroy

themselves through exposure to corrupting doctrines. In fact,

however, a significant number of people who have found the truth

which has made them free are strongly motivated to interfere with

the flow of information in society.

 

     For one thing, this person knows the truth. A position of

such moral certainty may well create a virtual obligation to

attempt to save others from the mischief that will result by

making false information available. Secondly, the person may wish

to proselytize others to join the elite group of those who have

been made free by the truth. Part of this process would involve 

enhancing access to true information while interdicting that

which is false. Finally the person may be insecure in his

allegiance to the true way. He may wish to act the censor to

avoid exposure to information that would tempt him into

backsliding.

 

     Whatever the particular motive of the star in this

morality play, it can be sure that there are good reasons for him

to act the role of the censor. The victims of the piece, then,

become any persons who are persuaded of the truth of false ideas,

and the villains are the persons who are responsible for the

production of such ideas and individuals, like librarians, who

promote and disseminate them. Of course, the stars of the play

are not always in agreement about which ideas are the most

truthful. That depends on the particular truths that have been

revealed to them. They often can agree, however, on a set of

ideas that they all consider false. This provides the foundation

for a coalition of censorship against the villains, including the

librarian, who would interfere with F2 freedom by promoting

information that is threatening to the ideals from which that

freedom derives.

 

     At this point, it may be appropriate to ask what has been gained

by the work that has been done this far. The search for an explanatory

model of the conflict between censor and librarian has been advanced

to the degree that each  of the morality plays which dramatize the

conflict can be seen to derive from a legitimate but contrasting

definition of freedom. This advance may be even more significant than

that, because if it is sound, it disposes of the question of which

position is right. It has been noted that both definitions of freedom

have a long historical tradition of accepted use that has been

carefully documented. (fn 15 INTFREE) This suggests that both

positions are valid.

 

     In fact, our careful reader will also have noted by now that the

two attitudes regarding freedom represent extreme positions in the

continuum that exists along the axis of social attitudes

conventionally labeled liberal and conservative. F1 represents a

classic statement of the nature of freedom as it is defined at the

liberal pole of the continuum. F2 is a conservative statement of the

same concept. We all know that the dynamic interaction between

conservative and liberal attitudes is central to our political system.

Many thoughtful persons have been intuitively aware that the struggle

between the ideal of intellectual freedom and the forces of censorship

had been related to differences between liberal and conservative

political attitudes.

 

     What this advanced model of the conflict demonstrates is that the

struggle can be defined in more specific terms related to differing

legitimate conceptions of the meaning of freedom. This insight

suggests that further exploration of the relationship between F1 and

F2 may provide our conflict model with an external power of

explanation.  While the meanings of F1 and F2 are distinct and may

even be mutually exclusive, it is not necessarily correct to assume

that they have no relationship to one another. Furthermore, the

persistence of each suggests that society's well-being requires

manifestations of both orders. What is the nature of the relationship

that binds F1 and F2? What do the two concepts of freedom have in

common that commands the ongoing interest of society? The definitions

that have been offered for the two concepts should offer a beginning

for the consideration of these questions. The most obvious point that

each definition shares is the power to act in some way without

interference from external agents. In the case of F1, the power

is to act as one chooses in the pursuit of individual good as it

is perceived by the actor. In the case of F2, the power is to act

according to one's acquired wisdom in pursuit of a moral ideal.

 

     Other points that the definitions have in common are related to

polar opposites. The power to act is directed in F1 toward the pursuit

of diversity. In F2, it is directed toward the pursuit of unity. In

the case of F1 the barrier to action is external coercion. In F2 the

barrier to action is insufficient personal integrity or wisdom to

pursue successfully the specified moral ideal. This is an internal

obstacle. F1 requires only that the individual exercise his/her active

will in order to initiate an action. F2 requires that the individual

exercise an acquired virtue or wisdom in order to initiate action.

 

     Historically, the two conceptions of freedom have been treated by

most philosophers as independent, distinctive and unique. Discussion and

debate have dealt with some form of one or the other while the

opposing form has been excluded. The foregoing analysis, however,

demonstrates that F1 and F2 seem to be related structurally. The two

definitions either share characteristics, as in the question of the

capacity to act without interference, or they are concerned with

consequences whose polar opposition suggests a set of mirror images:

unity versus diversity; external versus internal conditions;

inherent versus acquired capability.

 

     These similarities between F1 and F2 definitions recall the

intuitive connection between liberal and conservative attitudes about

freedom that was noted earlier. They reinforce the suspicion that the

term "freedom" is not merely a word that happens to be used to

describe similar but unrelated discrete concepts of F1 and F2. I think

the construction of a useful model for conflicts related to

intellectual freedom can be enhanced if F1 and F2 are considered

elements that comprise a more intricate representation of freedom.

Suppose that the concept of freedom refers to a multidimensional

holistic complex of characteristics, a dynamic action oriented system

in a state of tension between diversity and unity, between external

and internal controls, between will and wisdom as motivating forces.

Call this freedom complex Fc. Fc, with its set of opposing forces in

tension, can be considered a homeostatic system.

 

     The incorporation of the homeostatic Fc component completes the

explanatory model that is being constructed to advance understanding

of the conflict between intellectual freedom advocates and censors.

(fig. x illustrates the finished model) F1 and F2 are two distinctive

definitions of freedom that provide the elements for a pair of

morality plays about the role of freedom and information in our

society. In the first play, F1 is used to justify an argument for the

sanctity of intellectual freedom in the society against the incursions

of the villainous censor. In the second play, F2 is used to justify an

argument for the responsible exercise of censorship to protect society

against the excesses of villainous purveyors of dangerous

misinformation. The two conflicting morality plays oppose one another

in a homeostatic system. The system is driven by energy that is

provided by political input from citizens with varying degrees of

liberal and conservative attitudes toward the nature and amount of

freedom that should prevail in the society.

 

     If this model is valid, the F1 ideal of intellectual freedom,   

where any individual has the power to express or pursue any idea

without interference, is protected from becoming the semantic or

ideological equivalent of the tower of babel by the countervailing

effect of F2 principles which provide for the expression of only those

ideas that are judged to be right by an ideal standard arrived at

through wisdom or virtue.  Protection against the oppressive

consequences of a narrowly determined course of action that might

result from extreme applications of F2 principles is provided by the

wide range of choices that is a condition of F1.

 

     If this model is a reasonable reflection of reality, there is a

temptation to say that the issue of responsible action for librarians

and others concerned with protecting the role of intellectual freedom

in our society is merely hypothetical. It can be argued that the

system is in place and being regulated by forces over which

individuals have little control. Such an attitude, however, fails to

take into account the fact that all the actions in this philosophical

drama are also elements in the energy field that provides the power to

drive the homeostatic model. If individuals are not active advocates

of a particular position, the system loses vitality and flexibility in

its capacity to maintain stability.

 

     As a practical matter, the model that has been described here

does not operate in isolation. The question of the degree of

intellectual freedom that shall be in effect within the society is a

political issue. In order to illuminate successfully the application

of this model to the professional responsibility of librarians, it is

necessary to provide some common understanding of the political

environment in which the responsibility will be exercised.

 

     In our political system, attitudes are measured and given

authority through the legislative process. The decision of elected

officials are guided by the declared needs of those whom they

represent. Because there are always conflicting interests among

constituencies, the political process is an adversary procedure. Those

who wish to have an effect must succeed in capturing the attention of

government decision makers, and the most visible and aggressively

presented views are those which are most likely to be reflected in

government action. Moderate elements tend to be overwhelmed and

ignored when other perspectives are presented with fervent conviction.

 

     In the case of matters related to intellectual freedom, pressures

for political action are generated by constituencies which are strong

supporters of F1 and F2 positions. If the efforts of these lobbying

groups are within a similar range, the system will maintain a balance

which incorporates significant elements of F1 and F2. If support for

either dimension falters, the balance will shift toward the opposite

pole. If the shift goes too far in one direction, the theory of

homeostatic systems holds that the system will tumble out of control

into an even more extreme condition. Librarians and others who have a

strong interest in maintaining a societal balance which includes a

healthy degree of intellectual freedom must be prepared to engage in

organized and ongoing political activity to support the particular

dimensions of that freedom if they wish to preserve the system in

equilibrium.

 

     This argument for political activism is particularly crucial in

the case of the freedom conflict because of certain characteristics

associated with attitudes displayed by F1 and F2 advocates. Those who

support F2 precepts naturally attempt to live according to those

principles. Their freedom, after all, depends on how successfully they

conform to their moral ideal.  Although it is not true of all such

pathways, some prescriptions for living according to a moral standard

declare that theirs is the only legitimate course of action. Those who

have accepted such a set of values will believe that individuals

who have chosen other alternatives to guide their lives are

making a mistake. They are likely to consider it their moral

responsibility to attempt to correct such mistakes by every means

that is legally at their disposal. This is the motivation that

encourages them to act as censors for society. The morality play

in which they see themselves as playing a role does not encourage

open-mindedness.

 

     Librarians and other F1 supporters of the ideal of intellectual

freedom do not possess the same kind of single-minded dedication to

political activism. Our guiding morality play features an ideal of

respect for everyone's interests. We are inclined toward a laissez-

faire political attitude. What we need to understand, however, is that

if the model that has been developed here is valid, we do not have the

luxury of indulging our liberal ideals within the political arena.

Successful prosecution of our professional mission to provide society

with access to a full range of ideals depends on F1 values. These

values will remain secure only if there is a balance between F1 and F2

in the society. Political activists motivated by an exclusive and

narrowly defined set of F2 principles are going to continue to bring a

high level of intensity to their political support for those

principles. If librarians and other F1 supporters are going to

maintain a healthy homeostatic balance within the Fc system,

we need to match that intensity with a strong commitment of our

own.

 

     The thinking that informs this essay was originally

triggered by dissatisfaction with the conventional rationale for

a librarian's professional obligation to support the ideal of

intellectual freedom as an abstract principle. The argument

seemed to be based on the need to accept completely an ideal

associated with a particular morality play, but the reasons

usually provided by the library profession have taken the form of

a moral imperative. They have not been accompanied by convincing

persuasion. As a consequence, there have been a lot of rhetorical

flourishes, but little that would encourage cooperation from a person

who is suspicious of the dangers associated with unchecked F1 freedom.

The analysis that has been offered here is intended to provide a

basis for a more practical foundation.

 

     Let me try to summarize the argument that has been sketchily

developed here. It begins with the realization that the morality play

that motivates librarians to embrace the idea of free access to

information is matched by a conflicting morality play that highlights

the positive societal benefits of censorship. This suggests the

description of a model that attempts to incorporate the conflicting

positions represented by the two morality plays. An investigation of

philosophical literature on freedom reveals that definitions of

freedom can be divided into two discrete categories. The first, here

labeled F1, defines freedom as the capacity to act without coercion.

It seems to be the freedom that is celebrated in the morality play

that is associated with intellectual freedom. The other category, F2,

defines freedom as the capacity to act in accordance with a defined

ideal of right action. This seems to be the freedom that underlies the

morality play which guides the actions of the censor.

 

     The enduring presence of both concepts of freedom within Western

society suggests that both kinds of freedom are essential elements of

the culture. I have labeled the combination of F1 and F2 freedoms the

Fc complex. For purposes of advancing a hypothetical model that will

include both F1 and F2, I have advanced the idea of Fc as an example

of a homeostatic system, in which F1 and F2 balance one another to

avoid extreme social emphasis on either F1 or F2. The model presumes

that both F1 and F2 are necessary ingredients for a self governing

society, and that each serves as a check against the destructive

excesses associated with the domination of the other. F2 deters F1

practice from deteriorating into license while F1 holds F2 from

developing into tyranny.

 

     The last step in this discussion requires application of the

proposed model in a practical political context that refers

specifically to the intellectual freedom related interests of

librarians.

 

-------------

BIBLIOGRAPHY FROM INTFREE (DRAFT 1) -- (draft 1 apparently has

not been saved in machine-readable form printed copies are on

file)

 

1. John S. Robotham and Gerald Shields. Freedom of Access to

Library Materials. New York, Neal-Schuman, 1982. pp. 17

 

2. "Intellectual Freedom and Censorship." Encyclopedia of

Library and Information Science. vol. 12. Chicago, American

Library Association, 1983. p.169.

 

3. Edwin Castagna. "Censorship, Intellectual Freedom and

Libraries." Advances in Librarianship. vol. 2. New York, Seminar

Press, 1971. p. 217.

 

4. David Berninghausen. Flight From Reason. Chicago, American

Library Association, 1975. p. xiv.

 

5. Intellectual Freedom Manual. Second Edition, Chicago, American

Library Association, 1974. p. vii

 

6. Georg Wilhelm Hegel. The Philosophy of History in Great Books

of the Western World. vol. 46. New York, Encyclopedia Britannica,

1952. p. 161.

 

7. Gerald C. McCallum, Jr. "Negative and Positive Freedom."

Philosophical Reviews 76 (1967) p. 312.

 

8. See, for example, Isaiah Berlin, "Two Concepts of Liberty" in

Four Essays on Liberty. London, Oxford University Press, 1969,

pp. 118-172; Bernhard P. Dauerhauer, "Relational Freedom," Review

of Metaphysics 36 (September 1982) 77-101; P.H. Partridge,

"Freedom," Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Glencoe, Free Press, 1967,

pp.221-225; Felix E. Oppenheim, Dimensions of Freedom, an

Analysis, New York, St. Martin's, 1961; and most notably,

Mortimer J. Adler, The Idea of Freedom: a Dialectical Examination

of the Conception of Freedom, Garden City, Doubleday, 1958.

 

9. Berlin

 

10. Adler

 

11. Dauenhauer, p. 77 ff.

 

12. Immanuel Kant, Preface and Introduction to the Metaphysical

Elements of Ethics, with a Note on Conscience in Great Books of

the Western World, vol. 42. p. 378.

 

13. John Stuart Mill. On Liberty in Great Books of the Western

World. vol. 43. pp. 267-323.

 

14. John Milton. Areopagitica in Great Books of the Western

World. vol. 32. pp. 379-412.

 

15. Adler

 

16. Legal remedies may be invoked, but they do not constitute

examples of corrective energy in themselves. The energy resides

in society's movement toward F2, creating the momentum for new

laws, as well as other appropriate countermeasures.

 

17. "Public" as used here refers to all libraries supported by

public funds, whether they are associated with educational

institutions, other governmental enterprises or are free

community libraries.

 

18. Dauenhauer. p. 95.

 

19. It was only in this context that I began to understand the

wisdom of presidential candidate Barry Goldwater's 1964 remark,

"Extremism in the defense of liberty is no vice." The New York

Times. July 17, 1964. p. 1.

 

    

----------------------------

 

NOTE: THOMAS, CAL. BOOK BURNING. 1983. definition of intellectual

freedom -- "a spiritual dimension involving transcendent values .

. ." p. 36.

 

NOTE: DAVIS, DONALD G. "INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM AND EVANGELICAL

FAITH." CHRISTIAN LIBRARIAN (NOV.1985/FEB. 1986) pp. 3-6 for

discussion of evangelical point of view in favor of intellectual

freedom. copy in INTFREET file

 

also : JOHNSON, JAMES R. "A RATIONALE FOR CENSORSHIP IN CHRISTIAN

LIBRARIES." THE CHRISTIAN LIBRARIAN (FEB. 1981) pp. 28-34, which

includes a "concise summary of the Christian view of intellectual

freedom by John R Stott --pp. 30-31 -- which maps very well into

the F2 definition.  copy in INTFREET file

 

 

[rev. 1/04; © j.a. nelson 2004]