Zeno argues that it is impossible for a runner to traverse a race course. His reason is that
there is no motion, because that which is moving must reach the midpoint before the end (6=A25, Aristotle, Physics 239b11-13).
Why is this a problem? Because the same argument can be made about half of the race course: it can be divided in half in the same way that the entire race course can be divided in half. And so can the half of the half of the half, and so on, ad infinitum.
So a crucial assumption that Zeno makes is that of infinite divisibility: the distance from the starting point (S) to the goal (G) can be divided into an infinite number of parts.
How did Zeno mean to divide the race course? That is, which half of the race course Zeno mean to be dividing in half? Was he saying (a) that before you reach G, you must reach the point halfway from the halfway point to G? This is the progressive version of the argument: the subdivisions are made on the right-hand side, the goal side, of the race-course.
Or was he saying (b) that before you reach the halfway point, you must reach the point halfway from S to the halfway point? This is the regressive version of the argument: the subdivisions are made on the left-hand side, the starting point side, of the race-course.
If he meant (a), the progressive version, then he was arguing that the runner could not finish the race. If he meant (b), the regressive version, then he was arguing that the runner could not even start the race. Either conclusion is repugnant to reason and common sense, and it seems impossible to ascertain which version Zeno had in mind.
But it turns out that it really doesnt matter which version Zeno had in mind. For although this may not be obvious, the conclusions of the two versions of the argument are equivalent. Let us see why.
Since Zeno was generalizing about all motion, his conclusion was either (a) that no motion could be completed or (b) that no motion could be begun. But in order to begin a motion, one has to complete a smaller motion that is a part of it. For consider any motion, m, and suppose that m has been begun. It follows that some smaller initial portion of m has been completed; for if no such part of m has been completed, m could not have yet begun. Hence, if no motion can be completed, then none can be begun.
It is even more obvious that if no motion can be begun, then none can be completed. So the conclusion of (a) (no motion can be completed) entails, and is entailed by, the conclusion of (b) (no motion can be begun). That is, the two conclusions are logically equivalent. Hence we neednt worry about how Zeno wanted to place the halfway points.
R |
the runner |
S |
the starting point (= Z0) |
G |
the end point |
Z1 |
the point halfway between S and G |
Z2 |
the point halfway between Z1 and G |
Zn |
the point halfway between Zn-1 and G |
Z-run |
a run that takes the runner from one Z-point to the next Z-point |
Alternatively, one might object to (1) on the grounds that passing through all the Z-points (even though there are infinitely many of them) does not constitute making an infinite number of Z-runs. The reason might be that after you keep halving and halving the distance, you eventually get to distances that are so small that they are no larger than points. But points have no dimension, so no run is needed to cross one. But this is a mistake. For every Z-run, no matter how tiny, covers a finite distance (>0). No Z-run is as small as a point.
So we have established that the first premise is true. (Note: this does not establish that R can actually get from S to G. It only establishes that if he does, he will make all the Z-runs.)
There are three possible reasons that might be given in support of (2).
To see why one might think that Zeno had (a) in mind, we will examine a related argument that he actually gave: his argument against plurality. We will then return to the race course.
Go to next lecture
on Zeno against plurality
Go to previous
lecture on Parmenides, Stage 2
Return to the PHIL 320 Home Page
Copyright © 2002, S. Marc Cohen